100% de satisfacción garantizada Inmediatamente disponible después del pago Tanto en línea como en PDF No estas atado a nada
logo-home
EC345: W6-W10 notes $12.33
Añadir al carrito

Notas de lectura

EC345: W6-W10 notes

 0 veces vendidas
  • Grado
  • Institución

Leture, seminar and reading notes for weeks 6-10 of behavioural economics

Vista previa 4 fuera de 58  páginas

  • 12 de julio de 2022
  • 58
  • 2021/2022
  • Notas de lectura
  • Alexander dobson
  • 6-10
  • Desconocido
avatar-seller
Subjective well-being and happiness
Utility in Economics
● Jeremy Bentham: utility as hedonic pleasure/pain (directly measurable)
● Neoclassical revolution: abstraction of value via marginal utility
○ Maximising “bang for your buck”
○ Gossen, Stanley Jevons, Walras, Menger
● 20th century micro theory separated psychology and economics
○ Preference as minimal required structure
○ Representative utility only as ordinal (not cardinal) object
○ No assumptions about preferences
■ Utility of individual i is a function of consumption of individual i
○ Preferences defined as-if revealed in observed choice behaviour
○ Rejection of hedonistic assumptions of Benthamite Utility
● 1970s onwards: behavioural economics, happiness economics (Easterlin,
Kahneman, Oswald, Layars)

Cardinal and ordinal utility
● Cardinalism → utility is objective and quantifiable
○ Allows interpersonal comparison
○ Necessary for social welfare functions/public choice
○ Not necessary to service demand functions
○ Good for economics beyond behaviour → quality of outcome
● Ordinalism → utility is in terms of relative value (represents preferences)
○ Sufficient to derive demand/explore the interaction of demand+supply
○ Useful for economic theory
○ Omits the strength of preferences/experiences

Bentham: experienced utility
● Well being as experienced utility
○ Nature of value: hedonic/affective, evaluative/cognitive, eudaimonic
■ Hedonic/affective: emotional well-being
■ Evaluative/cognitive: well-being as life evaluation
■ Eudaimonic: rank yourself on a scale
● Temporal issue: immediate (instant utility), global (total utility)
○ Global → possibility of systematic errors in recollection
○ Possibility of systematic errors in forecasting

Multi-dimensional well-being (Stiglitz et al, 2010)
● Full account of well-being should consider these dimensions simultaneously:
○ Material living standards (income, consumption, wealth)

, ○ Health, education, personal activities (+ work)
○ Social connections/relationships
○ Environment (present and future)
○ Political voice and governance
○ Insecurity (economic and physical)

Subjective well-being: measurement by report
● Objective (conditions, capabilities) and subjective (experience) dimensions of
well-being are important
● Simple, direct measure of subjective well-being: by report
○ Responses to a survey-style question
○ Different techniques for obtaining the report
■ Face-to-face, postal or telephone survey
■ Momentary evaluation (experience sampling, ecological
momentary assessment)
■ Day reconstruction method: subjects keep a diary and break the
day into episodes. Report activities and feelings in that episode
■ U-index measures how much time people spend doing
unpleasant activities
● Different questions approach different concepts
○ Time frame → immediate, global, local
○ Nature of the quality of experience → hedonic, evaluative,
eudaimonic

Distribution of British life-satisfaction levels
● Most report themselves as being pretty happy
● May be underreporting of those who are less happy

The reporting function
● Subjective well-being data is censored reports of an assumed underlying,
unobservable experience utility construct
○ Censored: can only take certain values → no curvature
● r =r (h ,( y , z ,c ))+ e
○ r ( .) → reporting function
○ h( .) → underlying happiness function
○ y → socioeconomic determinants
○ z → demographic and personal characteristics
○ c → other relevant contextual factors
○ e → individual specific error term to communicating happiness

Modelling ordinal categorical dependent variables
● Reported subjective well-being as a discrete dependent variable. Options:
○ Binary discrete choice model → LPM, logit, probit

, ○ Ordinal outcome discrete choice model → ordered logit/probit
○ OLS as an indicative approximation, especially if it is a sizeable scale
■ Check the results are consistent with discrete choice methods

Subjective well-being measurement issues
● Interpersonal comparability
○ Interpretation of the question varies (translation issues if cross-country)
○ Scale may be used differently
● Bounded scale
● Observed sensitivity to context, mood, ordering effects, priming
● Possible deliberate or subconscious distorted report due to social context
○ Social desirability bias
○ May be affected by if measurement is face-to-face/by phone etc
● Global reports: errors in recollection and aggregation
○ Focusing illusion: salient measures (income) may be overweighted
○ Peak-end bias: value of remembered utility is overweighted by the
peak and end value
■ Remembered utility: utility a person thinks an event gave them
● Inevitably some error but plausible averages are found over large samples
○ Errors are not a huge issue unless they are systematic

Why are subjective well-being measures valuable?
● Validity: correlated with other well-being measures
○ Physical evidence of affection (smiling/laughing/electrical brain activity)
○ Independent evaluations
○ Self-reported health and sleep quality
○ Recent positive changes in circumstances
● Reliability over time: moderate 2-week correlation
● State-level subjective well-being effect is correlated with state-level quality of
life (calculated with non-subjective data)
● Common patterns over a wide range of datasets: U-shape with age

Subjective well-being and objective well-being
● Oswald and Wu (2010) compare life satisfaction data with state-level imputed
quality-of-life ranking
○ Life satisfaction data: 1.3 million random Americans from the BRFSS
(2005-08)
● Gabriel et al (2003) calculate the state-level quality of life calculated using
non-subjective data
○ Rank states from 1-50
○ Use many factors → weather, state park visitor numbers,
commute time, crime etc
● State quality of life ranking + life satisfaction data have a strong positive
correlation

, Subjective well-being as a measure of Choice utility
Benjamin et al (2012)

Questions
● Does (neoclassical) Choice Utility and SWB-measured utility coincide?
● Do people choose what they think would maximise their SWB?

Method
● 13 hypothetical scenarios with 2 alternatives, exploring trade-offs of factors
important in well-being (income, housing, sleep, commute, time with friends)
● Samples from 3 populations:
○ Students
○ Patients in a doctor’s waiting room
○ Nationally representative sample interviewed by phone
● Respondents are asked which alternative they would choose, and under
which they anticipate greater SWB
○ No possibility for indifference (may exaggerate the difference)
● Test whether rankings coincide

Example
● Trade-off between sleep and income
● Scenario 1: Jobs that are almost the same, but with different hours + wages
● Option 1: $80,000 a year. Reasonable hours → 7.5 hours of sleep per
night
● Option 2: $140,000 a year. Unusual hours → 6 hours of sleep per night

Findings
● Choice and anticipated well-being was consistent 83% of the time
○ 20% of choices had a discrepancy between choice + anticipated well-
being
● When controlling for own happiness, other factors are significant on choice
and subjective well-being → family happiness and social life
○ Own happiness: most important factor, explains the majority of choice
● ‘Life satisfaction‘ is a better predictor of choice than ‘Happiness measures’
● Predicted SWB coincide least with choices when students are asked
questions that are related to important decisions in their life
○ Respondents are more likely to pick higher income or ‘more money’
alternatives even if they think it has a lower predicted SWB

Conclusions
● People do not seek to maximise SWB exclusively (at least as measured here)
○ SWB is a uniquely important argument in the utility function

Los beneficios de comprar resúmenes en Stuvia estan en línea:

Garantiza la calidad de los comentarios

Garantiza la calidad de los comentarios

Compradores de Stuvia evaluaron más de 700.000 resúmenes. Así estas seguro que compras los mejores documentos!

Compra fácil y rápido

Compra fácil y rápido

Puedes pagar rápidamente y en una vez con iDeal, tarjeta de crédito o con tu crédito de Stuvia. Sin tener que hacerte miembro.

Enfócate en lo más importante

Enfócate en lo más importante

Tus compañeros escriben los resúmenes. Por eso tienes la seguridad que tienes un resumen actual y confiable. Así llegas a la conclusión rapidamente!

Preguntas frecuentes

What do I get when I buy this document?

You get a PDF, available immediately after your purchase. The purchased document is accessible anytime, anywhere and indefinitely through your profile.

100% de satisfacción garantizada: ¿Cómo funciona?

Nuestra garantía de satisfacción le asegura que siempre encontrará un documento de estudio a tu medida. Tu rellenas un formulario y nuestro equipo de atención al cliente se encarga del resto.

Who am I buying this summary from?

Stuvia is a marketplace, so you are not buying this document from us, but from seller bethwalton. Stuvia facilitates payment to the seller.

Will I be stuck with a subscription?

No, you only buy this summary for $12.33. You're not tied to anything after your purchase.

Can Stuvia be trusted?

4.6 stars on Google & Trustpilot (+1000 reviews)

45,681 summaries were sold in the last 30 days

Founded in 2010, the go-to place to buy summaries for 15 years now

Empieza a vender

Vistos recientemente


$12.33
  • (0)
Añadir al carrito
Añadido