100% satisfaction guarantee Immediately available after payment Both online and in PDF No strings attached
logo-home
Good has no objective meaning - Discuss. £8.44   Add to cart

Essay

Good has no objective meaning - Discuss.

 9 views  0 purchase
  • Institution
  • OCR

An A** 40-mark A-Level Ethics essay dissecting as to whether 'good' has meaning and, if so, the extent of this meaning. From the Meta-ethics topic within the OCR RS curriculum. Written by an A-Level student who achieved an A* in A-Level Religious Studies (a.k.a Philosophy and Ethics) (2022) and a ...

[Show more]

Preview 1 out of 3  pages

  • August 31, 2022
  • 3
  • 2022/2023
  • Essay
  • Unknown
  • A+
All documents for this subject (111)
avatar-seller
hannahdobson
“Good has no objective meaning.” Discuss.

Whilst normative ethics addresses the question of what one should do in order
to achieve ‘good’, Meta-ethics seeks to determine what ‘goodness’ actually is.
Cognitivism is a meta-ethical view postulating that moral statements express a
proposition that is either true or false, thereby arguing that the ‘good’ is uni-
versally knowable and meaningful. However, the extent to which goodness has
meaning proves divisive due to the differing views within the various forms of
cognitivism, such as ethical naturalism and intuitionism. Non-cognitivists pro-
pound the contrasting view that ‘good’ has no meaning at all, reinforcing that
the question, ‘what is good?,’ is contentious and complex, thus, it necessitates
deep examination.

An unconvincing argument against the statement is the naturalist belief that
ethical statements have the same meaning as non-ethical statements, as both
are factual and can be verified. The good, therefore, has objective meaning be-
cause it can be proven true or false evidentially. Thomas Aquinas’ Primary Pre-
cepts are naturalist positions as each universal precept has naturally morally
‘good’ qualities. Ethical naturalism can be seen within natural law through
Aquinas’ belief in a God-given order and his advocation for the study of the
world, and so the study of the good, in order to understand human purpose.
The ethical naturalist, F.H Bradley (1846-1924), lends weight to this argument
as he supports the idea that one’s moral duty can be known through observa-
tion, “What he has to do depends on what his place is, what his function is, and
all that comes from his station in the organism.” He argues that what is ‘good’
for a person comes from who they are, thereby supporting the idea that good-
ness is natural, observable and objective. However, this argument is critically
weakened by Hume’s Naturalistic Fallacy which refutes Bradley’s argument,
and naturalism as a whole, through emphasising that one cannot derive an
‘ought’ from an ‘is’. Thus, the fact that society determines what is good for any
given person does not mean that it is right in doing so. Furthermore, the natu-
ralist argument is equally restricted by G.E Moore (1873-1958), in Snare’s ‘The
Nature of Moral Thinking’ (1992), he attacks naturalism by asking, “If ‘good’
meant ‘pleasant’, then asking ‘Are pleasant things always good?’, would be
silly. But… the question, ‘Are pleasant things always good?’, is not silly - it
marks some real issue.” Moore calls this question of “is it good?” an “open
question” and thus differentiates moral from natural values because one can
always question the goodness of natural properties. This criticism therefore
weakens the argument and strongly highlights the view that goodness is a
‘non-natural’ property which is indefinable, contrary to the objective meaning
that naturalists seek to assert.

Intuitionism somewhat successfully expresses a strong argument that ‘good’
has subjective meaning. G.E Moore argues that ‘good’ is a simple, unanalysed
property, akin to a primary colour. Moore states that “If I am asked ‘what is
good?’, my answer is that good is good, and that is the end of the matter.” Or if
I am asked ‘How is good to be defined?’ My answer is that it cannot be de-
fined”, highlighting that the ‘good’ cannot be determined through sense evi-
dence. Yet, he argues one can still use self-evident moral intuition in order to
intuit whether a moral statement is true or false, reinforcing the ‘good’ as sub-
jectively meaningful. This argument is strengthened by H.A Prichard (1871-

The benefits of buying summaries with Stuvia:

Guaranteed quality through customer reviews

Guaranteed quality through customer reviews

Stuvia customers have reviewed more than 700,000 summaries. This how you know that you are buying the best documents.

Quick and easy check-out

Quick and easy check-out

You can quickly pay through credit card for the summaries. There is no membership needed.

Focus on what matters

Focus on what matters

Your fellow students write the study notes themselves, which is why the documents are always reliable and up-to-date. This ensures you quickly get to the core!

Frequently asked questions

What do I get when I buy this document?

You get a PDF, available immediately after your purchase. The purchased document is accessible anytime, anywhere and indefinitely through your profile.

Satisfaction guarantee: how does it work?

Our satisfaction guarantee ensures that you always find a study document that suits you well. You fill out a form, and our customer service team takes care of the rest.

Who am I buying these notes from?

Stuvia is a marketplace, so you are not buying this document from us, but from seller hannahdobson. Stuvia facilitates payment to the seller.

Will I be stuck with a subscription?

No, you only buy these notes for £8.44. You're not tied to anything after your purchase.

Can Stuvia be trusted?

4.6 stars on Google & Trustpilot (+1000 reviews)

77254 documents were sold in the last 30 days

Founded in 2010, the go-to place to buy revision notes and other study material for 14 years now

Start selling
£8.44
  • (0)
  Add to cart